INTRODUCTION
The field called applied ethics
has so many sub branches under it, for instance, under applied ethics we have
the field called business ethics, medical ethics, legal ethics, journalistic
ethics among many others. However, various branches of applied ethics or better
still various profession have their own language and axioms guiding them.
Consequently, this leads us to the term or concept known as paternalism.
Paternalism is one that arises in many different areas of our personal and
public life. As such, it is an important realm of applied ethics. But it also
raises certain theoretical issues. Perhaps the most important is: what powers
it is legitimate for a state, operating both coercively and in terms of
incentives, to possess. It also raises questions about the proper ways in which
individuals, either in an institutional or purely personal setting, should
relate to one another. How should we think about individual autonomy and its
limits? What is it to respect the personhood of others? What is the trade-off,
if any, between regard for the welfare of another and respect for their right
to make their own decisions?
WHAT
PATERNALISM IS
Paternalism is the interference
of a state or an individual with another person, against their will, and
defended or motivated by a claim that the person interfered with will be better
off or protected from harm. The issue of paternalism arises with respect to
restrictions by the law such as anti-drug legislation, the compulsory wearing
of seatbelts, and in medical contexts by the withholding of relevant
information concerning a patient's condition by physicians. At the theoretical
level it raises questions of how persons should be treated when they are less
than fully rational.
The analysis of paternalism
involves at least the following elements. It involves some kind of limitation
on the freedom or autonomy of some agent and it does so for a particular class
of reasons. As with many other concepts used in normative debate determining
the exact boundaries of the concept is a contested issue.
And as often is the case the
first question is whether the concept itself is normative or descriptive. Is
application of the concept a matter for empirical determination, so that if two
people disagree about the application to a particular case they are disagreeing
about some matter of fact or of definition? Or does their disagreement reflect
different views about the legitimacy of the application in question?
While it is clear that for some to
characterize a policy as paternalistic is to condemn or criticize it, which
does not establish that the term itself is an evaluative one. As a matter of
methodology it is preferable to see if some concept can be defined in
non-normative terms and only if that fails to capture the relevant phenomena to
accept a normative definition.
Examples of paternalism
include laws requiring the use of motorcycle helmets, a parent forbidding their
children to engage in dangerous activities, and a psychiatrist confiscating
sharp objects from someone who is suicidally depressed.
Thus, in stranford
encyclopedia of philosophy, we are introduced to the concept of paternalism by
the following conditions or illustration; an
analysis of X acts paternalistically towards Y by doing (omitting)
Z:
- Z (or its omission) interferes with the liberty or autonomy of Y.
- X does so without the consent of Y.
- X does so just because Z will improve the welfare of Y (where this includes preventing his welfare from diminishing), or in some way promote the interests, values, or good of Y.
Condition one is the trickiest to
capture. Clear cases include threatening bodily compulsion, lying, withholding
information that the person has a right to have, or imposing requirements or
conditions. But what about the following case? A father, skeptical about the
financial acumen of a child, instead of bequeathing the money directly, gives
it to another child with instructions to use it in the best interests of the
first child. The first child has no legal claim on the inheritance. There does
not seem to be an interference with the child's liberty nor on most conceptions
the child's autonomy.
Or consider the case of a wife
who hides her sleeping pills so that her potentially suicidal husband cannot
use them. Her act may satisfy the second and third conditions but what about
the first? Does her action limit the liberty or autonomy of her husband?
The second condition is supposed
to be read as distinct from acting against the consent of an agent. The agent
may neither consent nor not consent. He may, for example, be unaware of what is
being done to him. There is also the distinct issue of whether one acts not
knowing about the consent of the person in question. Suppose the person in fact
consents but this is not known to the paternaliser.
The third condition also can be
complicated. There may be more than one reason for interfering with Y. In
addition to concern for the welfare of Y there may be concern for how Y's
actions may affect third-parties. Is the “just for” condition too strong? Or
what about the case where a legislature passes a legal rule for paternalistic
reasons but there are sufficient non-paternalistic reasons to justify passage
of the rule?
If, in order to decide on any of
the above issues, one must decide a normative issue, e.g. does someone have a
right to some information, then the concept is not purely descriptive.
Ultimately the question of how to refine the conditions, and what conditions to
use, is a matter for philosophical judgment. The term “paternalism” as used in
ordinary contexts may be too amorphous for thinking about particular normative
issues. One should decide upon an analysis based on a hypothesis of what will
be most useful for thinking about a particular range of problems. One might
adopt one analysis in the context of doctors and patients and another in the
context of whether the state should ban unhealthy foods.
THE
JUSTIFICATION OF PATERNALISM IN MEDICAL ETHICS
As we have seen the analysis of
paternalism seems to cut both ways. It is an interference with liberty which
might be thought to place the burden of proof on the paternalist. It is an act
intended to produce good for the agent which might be thought to place the
burden of proof on those who object to paternalism. It might be thought, as
Mill did, that the burden of proof is different depending on who is being
treated paternalistically. If it is a child then the assumption is that, other
things being equal, the burden of proof is on those who resist paternalism. If
it is an adult of sound mind the presumption is reversed.
Suppose we start from the
presumption that paternalism is wrong. The question becomes under what, if any,
circumstances, can the presumption be overcome? The possible answers are “under
no circumstances”, “under some circumstances”, and “under any circumstances”
The last seems very implausible.
Essentially it is the view that the fact that an act is (intended to be)
beneficial for a person, and does not affect or violate the interests of
others, settles the question of whether it may be done. Only a view which
ignores the means by which good is promoted, and the ethical status of such
means, can hold this. Any sensible view has to distinguish between good done to
agents at their request or with their consent, and good thrust upon them
against their will.
So the normative options seem to
be just two. Either we are never permitted to do good for others against their
wishes, and in ways which limit their liberty, or we are permitted to do so.
Why might one think that at least
the state may never do so? One might think so because of various beliefs about
the impossibility of in fact doing good for people against their will or
because one thinks that although possible to do good it is in fact inconsistent
with some normative standard which ought to prevail.
With respect to the impossibility
question one might believe either that it is not possible to do any good by
acting paternalistically or that although it is possible to do some good the
process will (almost) always produce bad which outweigh the good.
If one thought that almost)always
more harm than good is done by the state when it acts paternalistically this
raises the question of whether we can distinguish the conditions in which
(rarely) more good than harm is done and build that into our guidelines. If
this is possible, and so distinguishing does not create further harms which
outweigh the good produced, and we think, the only issue is good promotion we
should sometimes be paternalists. If it is impossible to distinguish the “good”
from the “bad” cases then, at least if we are rule consequentialists, we ought
not to have such a rule; and we ought not to try and make the distinctions on a
case by case basis.
But one might believe that the
question of whether more good than harm is produced is not simply an empirical
one. It depends on our understanding of the good of persons. If the good simply
included items such as longer life, greater health, more income, or less
depression, then it makes it look like an empirical issue. But if we conceive
of the good of individuals as including items such as being respected as an
independent agent, having a right to make decisions for oneself, or having
one's autonomy not infringed, then the issue of whether the agent is better off
after being `subjected to paternalism is partly a normative matter. One might
believe that one cannot make people better off by infringing on their autonomy
in the same way that some people believe one cannot make a person better off by
putting them in a Nozickian experience machine.
Kantian views are frequently
absolutistic in their objections to paternalism. On these views we must always
respect the rational agency of other persons. To deny an adult the right to
make their own decisions, however mistaken from some standpoint they are, is to
treat them as simply means to their own good, rather than as ends in
themselves. In a way anti-paternalism is already incorporated into Kantian
theories by their prohibition against lying and forces—the main instruments of
paternalistic interference. Since these instrumentalities are already denied
even to prevent individuals from harming others, they will certainly be
forbidden to prevent them from harming themselves. Of course, one may object to
the former absolutism while accepting the latter.
If one believes that sometimes
paternalism is justifiable one may do so for various kinds of theoretical
reasons. The broadest is simply consequentialist, i.e. more good than harm is
produced. A narrower justification is that sometimes the individuals (long-run)
autonomy is advanced by restricting his autonomy (short-run). So one might
prevent people from taking mind-destroying drugs on the grounds that allowing
them to do so destroy their autonomy and preventing them from doing so
preserves it. This is essentially Mill's argument against allowing people to
contract into slavery. Note that if the theory of the good associated with a
particular consequentialism is broad enough, i.e., includes autonomy as one of
the goods, it can be equivalent to the autonomy theory (assuming that the
structure of the autonomy view is a maximizing one).
A different theoretical basis is
(moral) contractualism. On this view if there are cases of justified
paternalism they are justified on the basis that we (all of us) would agree to
such interference, given suitable knowledge and suitable motivation. So, for
instance, it might be argued that since we know we are subject to depression we
all would agree, at least, to short-term anti-suicide interventions, to
determine whether we are suffering from such a condition, and to attempt to
cure it. More generally, we might accept what Feinberg called “soft
paternalism.” This is the view that when we are not acting fully voluntarily it
is permissible to intervene to provide information, or to point out defects in
our rationality, but that if we then do make a voluntary choice it must be
respected. Or we might agree to being forced to wear seat-belts knowing our
disposition to discount future benefits for present ones. The justification
here is neither consequentialist nor based simply on the preservation of
autonomy. Rather either kind of consideration may be taken into account, as
well as others, in determining what we would reasonably agree to.
Conclusively,
it is pertinent to note that paternalism as a concept greatly influences
medical ethics as it affects the autonomy of patients and most times could lead
to non-benevolence which is doing harm to others. From the above however, we
can see various reasons that some medical practitioners will seldom give to
carry out the act of paternalism.
REFERENCES:
‘Ethics’; Encyclopaedia
Britannica
‘Medical Ethics and Applied
Ethics’ in Stanford Encyclopaedia of philosophy
Applied Ethics; Perspectives from Asia and Beyond, Edited by Kohji
Ishihara and Shunzo Majima.
Copy right: Richard Oluseye Anthony (Department of Philosophy, University of Ibadan, Nigeria.)
No comments:
Post a Comment